(paper for B. Göcke and C.
Tapp, eds., The Infinity of God,
University of Notre Dame Press, 2017)
Robert M. Wallace
Abstract: This paper shows how Hegel’s
conception of infinity enables him to integrate science and religion, and the
“natural” and the “supernatural,” more explicitly and effectively than any
other well-known writer has done. (Though in retrospect one can see a similar
integration at work in the whole broadly Platonic tradition, of which Hegel is
an important member.) Through infinity and the “spirit” that’s structured by it
we see that science, religion, ethics, art, and philosophy are all necessary
aspects of a single self-determining reality, whose traditional name is “God.” Science,
religion, ethics, art, and philosophy all seek to “ascend” above one’s initial
opinions, appetites, and emotions, to something that’s truer, better, or more
beautiful. This ascent takes us beyond the ways in which we’re determined by
our biological antecedents and our environment, and thus it makes us
self-governing. By making us self-governing, it makes us real as ourselves, and in that sense it constitutes
a higher reality, which we call “God” because only it is fully itself, and not
a product of limits and thus of what’s other than itself. The essential role of
“ascent” in this reality corresponds to what’s traditionally called
“transcendence,” so that Hegel’s conception is neither atheist nor pantheist. But
the ascent connects nature and the “supernatural” (Hegel’s “Spirit”) in an
intelligible way, rather than leaving their relationship a mystery. And the
role of science in the ascent and in Spirit makes it clear that Hegel’s
conception is not anti-scientific. It merely prevents us from thinking of
science as the only form of ascent.
In this paper I’m going to outline how through
his conception of infinity and the “spirit” that’s structured by infinity, Hegel
integrates science and religion, and the natural and the supernatural, more
explicitly and effectively than any other well-known thinker has done. Though
in retrospect one can see a similar integration at work in the entire broadly
Platonic tradition of which Hegel is an important recent member.[1]
Through Hegel’s account of infinity and
“spirit” we see that science, religion, ethics, the arts, and philosophy are
all necessary (not points of view on, but) aspects
of a single self-determining reality, whose traditional name is “God.” This
is the essential proposal of the latter two thirds of Hegel’s Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1817
ff.), on “Nature” and “Spirit,” which derive their structure from his account
of Infinity in the first third of the Encyclopedia
(on “Logic”) and in his Science of
Logic (1812 ff.).[2]
Once one understands science, religion, etc. in this way, as aspects of the
ultimate reality, it makes no sense to try to delegitimize one of them by
appealing to another one. Since they belong together, each must be practiced in
a way that respects the others.
Because we have inklings of the integration
that Hegel achieves, he has an ongoing influence in widely disparate circles even
though there is very little agreement as to what exactly it is that he
integrates or how he does it. I hope that by presenting an accomplishment which
there is reason to impute to Hegel and which appears to have great cultural and
intellectual significance, I will encourage further work on this broad issue.
Including, of course, further exegetical work on the form that this
accomplishment takes in Hegel and in related thinkers.
1. An Ultimate Reality?
How can science, religion, ethics, the arts, and
philosophy all be necessary aspects of an ultimate “reality”?
They all seek to practice an “ascent” above
one’s initial opinions, appetites, and emotions, to something that’s truer, better
than, or more beautiful than those initial opinions, appetites, and emotions. By
“ascending” in this way, whether through truth, goodness, or beauty, we make
ourselves more able to govern ourselves, rather than being governed by whatever
external forces caused us to have our initial opinions, appetites, and emotions.
Insofar as we govern ourselves, in this way, we become more “real,” as
ourselves and not merely as products of our environment, than we would
otherwise be. Hegel points to this higher degree of reality with his doctrines
that “the finite is only by going
beyond itself,” as the infinite, and that “the finite is not the real, rather
the infinite is the real.”[3]
By which he means that when the finite “becomes infinite” by going beyond its
limiting relations to its circumstances, it “is” as itself, and not merely as
the product of those circumstances. We can call this more intensive reality
“ultimate,” because it includes the more familiar kinds of “reality” but goes
beyond them in a way that seems to be definitive. Nothing could be more real
than what by governing itself makes itself what it is.
By rising above external circumstances in this
way, science, religion, ethics, the arts, and philosophy all help to constitute
the ultimate reality. Let me emphasize, however, that to say that science etc.
help to constitute this reality is not to say that science etc., as finite, “human”
activities, are what’s real, and the “ultimate reality” derives its reality
from theirs. For in that case there wouldn’t be anything particularly
“ultimate” about it. Rather, “the finite is
only by going beyond itself,” as the infinite. Insofar
as science, etc., pursue truth, goodness, and so forth, they go beyond the
finite and (in ways that will become apparent as we go along) they are more
than what we normally think of as “ours.” And the result is that the ultimate
reality that they constitute is also more than merely human or merely ours, and
is, in fact, logically prior to (more fundamental and more real than) what is
finite, merely human, and, in the ordinary sense, ours.
In what follows, I will try to clarify this apparently
paradoxical proposal. To begin with, let’s look at how science, religion, etc.,
each contribute to something that deserves to be called an ultimate reality.
2. Science and the Arts as Aspects of the
Ultimate Reality
It’s not difficult to see how science is an
aspect of the ultimate reality that I’ve described. Insofar as science seeks
the truth, as such, rather than merely to satisfy our preexisting appetites or
confirm our preexisting opinions, it goes beyond those appetites and opinions
and reflects something that seems more our own than they are. We can let particular
appetite-satisfactions and opinions go while knowing that we ourselves are
still intact. But if we were to let our pursuit of truth go, we would become
automatons, no longer governing ourselves in a significant way but simply
reacting (through appetites and opinions) to the world that created us and
impinges on us, and thus no longer existing as “ourselves.”[4]
So our pursuit of truth expresses us ourselves, our self-government, more than externally-induced
appetites or opinions can do; and the same is true of the sciences, as particular
ways in which we pursue the truth. In this way the sciences help to constitute
something that’s more fully itself, and more real as itself, than what would otherwise be present.
Thus the idea that science shows or presupposes
that there is no higher or more ultimate reality is refuted by the practice of
science itself. For by rising above our externally-induced appetites and
opinions, science helps to constitute something that’s more self-governing, and
thus more real as itself and in a clear sense more ultimate than what lacks
science. And a world in which nothing pursued science or the truth as such
would be less self-governing and less real as itself than the world in which
they are pursued. Its contents would be determined by an apparently infinite
regress of causes, without anything that causes or governs itself.
Next, the arts. Insofar as they take us beyond
the satisfaction of bodily appetites or our needs for security, pride, and the
like, the arts seem to put us in a state that expresses “us” personally more
than our bodily appetites and emotional needs are likely to. For the body and our
emotional needs were presumably formed largely by prior bodies and by
experiences that came from outside us. Whereas by taking us beyond the body’s
appetites and externally induced emotional needs, the arts enable us to be less
dominated by external influences as such. This would explain the fact that we
find excellent works of art not merely pleasant or entertaining, but (as we
say) “inspiring.” By freeing us, to some degree, from merely external
influences, so that we can (as we say) be “creative” and “express ourselves,” the arts enable us to be more
fully ourselves and they thereby contribute to the reality that’s real “as
itself,” by not being governed by what’s other than it.
3. Religion as an Aspect of the Ultimate
Reality
With regard to religion, you might wonder how
it could contribute to our being fully ourselves. Doesn’t it do the opposite,
by directing us to be governed by something, such as a “God,” that’s other than
us? I want to suggest that even in the Abrahamic religions, with their focus on
a God who seems to be separate and set over against us, there is an important
sense in which this God in fact does or can function to make us more fully
ourselves.
It’s well known that religions in general urge
their followers to subordinate purely self-centered concerns to something
that’s higher or more inclusive. The moral teachings of Judaism, Christianity,
and Islam certainly do this. While they sometimes promise rewards and
punishments after death, their most exalted and most admired teachings
celebrate virtue itself as bringing us closest to God. The best-known and most
admired saying of Rabia of Basra, the eighth-century Sufi saint, is that she
wanted to “burn paradise and douse hell-fire, so that … God’s servants will
learn to see him without hope for reward or fear of punishment.”[5]
There is still the issue of the authority that
God seems to have in these religions, which sets God over against those who
must merely obey. Here, turning to Christianity, I would point out how in the
Christian scriptures, Jesus is reported as saying that “the kingdom of God is
within you” (Luke 17:21).[6]
St Paul is reported as approving the view that “in” God, “we live and move and
have our being” (Acts 17:28). And numerous early Christian writers wrote of the
possibility of our “becoming God” (theosis),
as something that was made possible by God’s “becoming man.”[7]
These latter formulations are in fact preserved and repeated in the Roman
Catholic Catechism and Mass. Similar formulations can be found in Jewish and Islamic
mystical writings and in Advaita Vedanta and Taoism.
None of these formulations encourage the common
idea that God is simply a separate being, one that “exists independently of”
humans. Nor does such an idea recommend itself if we want God to be infinite; for as Hegel points out, any
being that’s separate is ipso facto finite,
limited by its relation to the other beings, from which it’s separate. (That
relation being the relation of “being separate from” those beings.) This is Hegel’s critique of the “spurious
infinity” (schlechte Unendlichkeit)
which is conceived of as separate from the finite but is therefore limited by
its relation to the finite, and thus is finite itself.[8]
So Hegel, drawing on the “orthodox” texts that I mentioned and followed by modern
theologians like Paul Tillich and Karl Rahner, seeks a formulation that will preserve
God’s transcendence while not making God a “separate being.”[9]
4. Hegel’s Version of Transcendence: Beyond but
not Separate
The biggest obstacle to
understanding Hegel’s relation to religion is the widespread notion that if Hegel
is indeed serious about God, his “God” is “immanent” rather than
“transcendent,” and this sets him apart from what people take to be “orthodox”
religious thinking.[10]
It’s likely that writers who describe Hegel in this way think that a “transcendent”
God would be a being that’s separate from the world, as Hegel’s God is not.[11]
But as I’ve just pointed out, first, Hegel has a good reason to avoid thinking
of God as a separate being from the world (namely, that a separate being is
limited by what it’s separate from, and thus it’s not infinite), and second, the
Christian and other theistic traditions are by no means unanimous in thinking
of God as a separate being from the world. For (to cite the Christian doctrines
again) if God were a separate being, we could hardly “become God,” and it’s
difficult to imagine how God’s “kingdom” could be “within us.”
Nor is it clear that a
God who is not a separate being is therefore “immanent.” Hegel gives no
systematic role to the terms, “transcendence” and “immanence,” but if we look
for a central concern of his that corresponds to what we mean by “transcendence”
(such as passing beyond limits, or surpassing the material universe), it would
be the difference between the (truly) infinite and the finite.[12]
The infinite transcends or (as Hegel puts it) “goes beyond” the finite in that
it’s real as itself and not just as
the product of other things.[13]
Plato and Hegel both evidently intend to conceive of a reality that’s
“transcendent” in something like this sense, without being a “separate” or
“independently existing” being or beings. [14]
This intention makes it clear why Hegel is not,
as is sometimes suggested, a pantheist. The
vertical dimension whereby the infinite goes beyond the finite, prevents “everything” from being equally “divine,” as
it’s supposed to be in pantheism. Insofar as it’s a mere collection of finite
things, whether denumerable or otherwise, “everything” isn’t the kind of
infinity that Hegel is interested in, because it seems clear to him that only a
qualitative infinity, which produces
a different kind of being from finite beings, can invite worship and deserve to
be called divine.
But one still naturally
wants to know how something (call it, “B”) can go beyond something else (“A”) and
be “more real as itself” than A is, without being a separate being from A. The
answer is that this can be the case if B is A’s own going beyond its finitude, by
becoming infinite and real as itself.[15]
A can go beyond its finitude through rational self-government or the pursuit of
truth, such as I described earlier, in which A is guided by reason rather than
by whatever external forces caused it to have the opinions and appetites that it
started out with. If anything expresses A itself, rather than expressing
externally induced opinions or appetites, it’s A’s pursuit of truth. When it’s
guided by itself in this way, A as B
is real as itself, and in that sense
it’s more real than it was merely as the externally-guided, unthinking A. But
since B is A’s own going beyond its finitude, in this way, B is not a separate
being from A.
Presenting God in this
way, as the self-surpassing (becoming fully real) of finite things rather than
as a being that’s separate from finite things, is Hegel’s
way of interpreting (among others) the teachings that “the kingdom of God is within you” and that in God, “we live
and move and have our being.” The
kingdom of God is within us in the sense that we’re capable of rational
self-government, and we have our being in this God in the sense that it’s only
through our self-government “in” this God that we achieve full reality, full
being, as ourselves.
But we’re still talking about God, and not
merely about us, insofar as this full reality is always “above” a great part of
what we, as human beings, are. The finite “is
only by going beyond itself”:
Hegel is not reducing God to us as the finite beings that we ordinarily take
ourselves to be. Rather, he is elevating us (in part) to something beyond what
we ordinarily take ourselves to be. This is why the apparent paradox that I
mentioned, that the reality that’s more real than us is constituted by our
activities, is only apparent. For this ultimate reality is constituted by
activities in which we in fact go beyond our finite selves, to a higher degree
of reality than we normally possess.
I’ll say more about this in what follows. But
we can already see how Hegel’s version of transcendence identifies a core of
truth in religion which lends itself to integration with science, ethics, the
arts, and philosophy. It lends itself to this because it takes religion to be
promoting the surpassing of one’s everyday finite self, rather than promoting
submission to something that’s separate from oneself. This core of truth no
doubt contrasts with much conventional religious talk, but no advocate of religion
is likely to deny that religion encourages its followers to surpass their
everyday ways of thinking and functioning. Jesus (in Luke), St. Paul, Rabia,
and Hegel are simply defining with increasing precision what would be the
result of our doing that. They make it clear how one can speak meaningfully of
an ultimate reality that’s neither reducible to humans, as such, nor, as Karl
Rahner put it, a mere “member of the
larger household of all reality,” as it would be if it were an additional
being, separate from and alongside humans and the “world.”[16]
5. The Plato/Hegel “Philosopher’s God”: Love,
Faith, Prayer, etc.
As for the common objection that religious believers
will be left cold by a “philosopher’s God” such as one finds in Platonism and
in Hegel, several points need to be made. First of all, this kind of God is
characterized not only by the rational self-government or freedom that is
manifest in rising above pre-given appetites and opinions, but also by an
important kind of love. The reason for this love is made most explicit by
Hegel, in a variation on his critique of the supposed “infinity” that turns out
to be rendered finite by being opposed to finite beings. Hegel points out that
being separate from others is a way of being related to those others, so that
being guided by one’s separateness from others is a way of being guided by those others as others and, to that
extent, not being guided by oneself.[17]
So being guided by one’s separateness from others detracts from one’s
self-government.
But “self-centered” people and gods are, precisely, guided by their separateness from
others—they are concerned about themselves, and “not” (as they will tell you) concerned about those “others.” And to
that extent they are guided by (their
relation to) those others, and they fail to be self-governed. So people and gods who are fully self-governed will
not be self-centered. Rather, they will be, in effect, loving: they will treat
others the same way they treat themselves. In this way, freedom as
self-government translates into an important kind of love.[18]
Of course this also makes it clear how
being truly oneself entails ethics, in which we are expected (broadly) to treat
others as we treat ourselves.
Secondly, since the ultimate reality, which is
real “as itself,” is real in a way that everyday finite realities are not, one
could see it as the core of truth in the idea of God’s “creating” the world. By
its presence in and influence on the world, the ultimate reality gives the world
all of the “full” reality, reality “as itself,” that the world possesses.
Third, our adherence to the ultimate reality
that’s composed of freedom and love, despite the attractions of self-centered
appetites, opinions, and so forth, is equivalent to what traditional religion
calls “faith.” This is because our commitment to the ultimate reality is to
something that goes beyond our “all-too-human” nature, and which from the point
of view of that nature (that is, from the point of view of self-centered appetites
and opinions) has no evident authority at all.
Furthermore, turning away from those self-centered
appetites and opinions toward freedom and love is the equivalent of what’s
traditionally called “conversion.” The aid that we receive, in this faith and
conversion, from the freedom and love that are around us and hidden (as
potential) within us, is equivalent to what’s traditionally referred to as
“grace” and “salvation.” And our praise of this aid and our effort to be
receptive to it are what we traditionally call “worship” and “prayer.”
Critics often suggest that the Plato/Hegel God
is not a “personal” God. But the Plato/Hegel God is in fact much more personal
than we usually are, because, as Hegel tells us, it’s “supremely free.” Through
its freedom/love, it nurtures the
potential for “personhood” in everything, including us.[19]
In all of these ways, this “philosopher’s God” and
our dealings with it reproduce what we see in traditional religion. The only apparent
difference is that Plato and Hegel present it all in a more analytical vocabulary.
It seems reasonable to suggest that what’s most inspiring in traditional religious
stories and concepts may be, precisely, the transcendent, free, loving, and supreme
reality that Plato and Hegel show we’re able to experience.
Plus, as I’ve explained, what Plato and Hegel
describe has the advantage over the conventional conception of God as a
separate being that Plato’s and Hegel’s God is truly infinite, which is to say,
truly transcendent.
I realize that the view of Plato that I’m
suggesting here may be unfamiliar. Few present-day commentators on Plato focus
on the way in which Plato’s account of the soul, in book iv of the Republic, together with his account of
cognitive “ascent” in books vi and vii, shows how we can understand
“transcendence” as a process that takes place within the world rather than
simply in opposition to it. But this is the aspect of Platonism that Aristotle,
Plotinus, and Spinoza all develop in various ways, and which Hegel in his turn
conceptualizes through his account of true infinity and spirit.[20]
All of these thinkers are very serious about transcendence, and they all seek
to understand it as in some way taking place within reality or the world,
rather than flatly in opposition to reality or the world. It’s a dimension of
ascent, rather than a dualistic divide. For, as Hegel in particular spells out,
a dualistic divide prevents either of its components from truly transcending
the other.
6. Science and the Scientist, “Object” and
“Subject”
I must also acknowledge the natural response of
admirers of science to what I have been saying about science’s contribution to
the reality that’s fully itself and that’s traditionally called “God.” The
problem is that science doesn’t seem to recognize any such “ultimate reality”
as I have been describing. If science doesn’t recognize it, how can I say that science helps to constitute it? This puzzling state of
affairs fuels the suspicions towards “metaphysics” and religion which one often
encounters among people who admire the sciences.
The explanation of this puzzle is that
beginning with the scientific revolution in the seventeenth century, modern
science has made it its business to focus solely on “objects” and to ignore the
possible significance of its own rational activity—of the “subject,” as German
Idealists call it. The narrow focus on “objects” was initially intended as a
practical way of maximizing the likelihood of rapid progress within a delimited
area. Since then, however, it has come to be taken for granted, to such an
extent that a scientist who suggests that her own rational activity deserves
attention in its own right is likely to seem like an eccentric who is
distracting attention from the only true reality: that of “objects.” Science in
practice systematically excludes itself, its own rational activity, from the
realm of “objective realities” that it addresses.
When one puts it that way, it’s obvious that
such an exclusion can only be defended as a temporary expedient, not as an
established truth about what’s real. Surely an activity that claims to be fully
rational must ultimately address itself, the “subject,” as well as its
“objects.” And indeed this is just what the great modern philosophers have
tried to do, on behalf of science.
Kant’s way of addressing this issue, in his
three Critiques, was to keep the subject separate from its objects. Science as
he understood it was properly concerned only with objects, understood in a
Newtonian mechanistic way, while the subject had “moral faith” in certain
things about itself which mechanistic science could not know about the world as
such. The subject had moral faith in its freedom, responsibility, immortality,
and so forth. Kant’s thoughts, in the third Critique, about the “regulative”
role of teleology in understanding life, did not succeed in bridging the
fundamental divide between object and subject, and knowledge and “faith,” which
he had thus created. There was still
no way that one could have knowledge of oneself and of how one should act; one
could only have practical faith. But if one’s ideal is knowledge, then a “faith” that’s contrasted with knowledge
is bound to seem like a poor substitute for it. As a result of this unresolved
dualism of knowledge versus faith, it seems clear that Kant did not
successfully integrate science with ethics and religion.
One alternative, which
is often adopted, would be to exalt some kind of “faith,” as the key to
everything, over knowledge. As an
admirer of science, Kant wasn’t tempted to do this, so he remained stuck with
the problem of how to relate the two.
7. Hegel’s Platonic
Solution
A third approach, which
goes beyond Kant’s uncomfortable dualism and beyond the exaltation of faith,
was sketched by Hegel in his early essay, “Faith and Knowledge” (1802) and
systematically developed in his Science
of Logic and his Encyclopedia of the
Philosophical Sciences. Hegel was in effect returning to something like what
seems to have been Plato’s original solution to the problem. Hegel explains how
knowledge and faith, and object and subject each involve the other. Rather than
being belief in a separate and very powerful being, “faith,” in Hegel’s view,
is one’s commitment to the pursuit of
knowledge—and through knowledge, of
being oneself, and being real as oneself—as opposed to mere opinion, appetite-satisfaction,
and failure to be oneself. The “subject” that exhibits this commitment is far
from being merely “subjective” since, being real as itself, it has a more complete “reality” than mere “objects,” as
such, possess. Thus “faith” in this sense generates full reality, and gives rational
access to it as well. Rather than being opposed to knowledge or reason, this
faith is part and parcel of knowledge and reason.
In his major works
beginning with his Science of Logic, Hegel
investigates the central issue of what it is to be oneself, and to be real as
oneself.[21]
To begin with, he presents “becoming,” or coming-into-being and perishing, as
entailing a “something” that comes into being or perishes, and which thus is
determinate in some way (has a definite quality). The question then is, is the
something determinate in itself (an sich)
or through its relations to others (Sein-für-anderes)?
We might suppose that the
something could be determinate in itself by being separate from others, as
“finite” things are. But as I suggested earlier, this separation still connects
it to the others, because it constitutes a relation between them. So separation
and finitude don’t give us something that’s determinate entirely in itself. Rather,
they give us what amounts to an infinite regress, of which no part is fully
determinate by itself, and thus the “promise” of determinacy seems to be
endlessly postponed.
The qualitative infinite,
on the other hand, which involves no boundaries, promises to be determinate
entirely in itself. As I mentioned in connection with the common conception of
God as a separate being from us, it’s important not to conceive of the
“infinite” as another “being,” separate from finite beings and thus, in fact,
limited by its relation to them and not infinite. Hegel proposes that in order
to avoid this outcome and come up with a true
infinity, we must conceive of the infinite as the finite’s own going beyond its
finitude.[22]
Then there is no border between the two, and we have before us what Hegel at
one point calls “the fundamental principle of philosophy.”[23]
He calls it that because in it we finally have something that is what it is in
itself, rather than through its relations to others, but which at the same time
allows for the apparent multiplicity and reality of finite beings.
How can the finite “go
beyond its finitude”? Again as I suggested earlier, the finite can do this
through something like rational self-government. We are sometimes able to be
more self-determining, and thus to be what we are more “in ourselves,” by being
governed by our own thinking rather than by appetites or opinions that
originated outside us. Hegel here is drawing on Kant’s notion of rational
autonomy, in which the autonomous moral agent is governed by its own rational
nature rather than by inclinations that probably originated outside it. A
finite something that goes beyond its finitude, Hegel suggests, is like a
finite human being that goes beyond its initial appetites and opinions.[24]
There is something within the something which guides it, and through which it’s
no longer “finite,” no longer limited and determined by what’s around it.
The first signal that
such an inner guidance is possible is what Hegel calls (paraphrasing Kant and J.G.
Fichte) “the ought” (das Sollen). Kant
had made it clear that our inner guidance takes us beyond the realm of mere
“fact,” to a “morality” that his readers might be inclined to call a realm of “value.”
Likewise Hegel’s “infinite” is not a “fact.” Like the initial notion of something’s
being what it is “in itself” and not just through its relations to others, the
infinite or the Ought is an aspiration.
But it’s not “only” an aspiration, since it’s only through this aspiration that
anything, including the universe, can be what it is entirely in itself, and not
by reference to anything outside it. So that “value” and full reality are not
(as we commonly suppose) separate domains, but are intimately entwined.
In this way the Ought and
what follows it are the equivalent, in Hegel’s presentation, of the Good, which
Plato placed at the summit of reality. And indeed the Good itself appears in
that traditional Platonic role at the end of Hegel’s Science of Logic. It’s only through the aspirations that are associated
with the Good or the Ought that the soul, in Plato, or anything at all, in
Hegel, can be what it is entirely in itself. As Plato’s Good had enabled the
soul to be unified and to function as “itself,” the Ought and what follows it enable
Hegel’s something to be self-determined and “itself.”[25]
In this way, value plays an indispensable role in constituting what’s fully
real, in the sense of being real as itself. Here Hegel follows Plato and Aristotle
in identifying purposes, and value in general, as an essential aspect of
reality, rather than a separate domain as they are in David Hume or in Kant.
So where Hegel differs
from Kant is that by showing how the finite fails to be what it is in itself,
Hegel shows that only the (value-based) infinite is fully real, in the sense of
being real as itself. Knowing this, through Hegel’s exposition, and knowing
through our experience the freedom that constitutes the infinite full reality,
we know the infinite, our freedom, and
the highest reality, rather than (as in Kant’s account) merely having
“practical faith” in them. This knowledge of the finite’s relation to the
infinite creates a path from the finite to the infinite, an intelligible process
of “ascent,” in contrast to the unbridgeable duality between theoretical
knowledge and practical faith, which Kant had left us with.
We see this ascent from
finite to infinite again later in Hegel’s system as an ascent from Nature to
Spirit. As the true infinity is the self-surpassing of the finite, so Spirit is
the self-surpassing of Nature. And in each case, what propels this surpassing
is our effort to be fully ourselves, and in that sense fully “real.” So again
we have an intelligible process of ascent, this time from Nature to Spirit.
By presenting this
process of ascent from Nature to Spirit, Hegel responds to the standard charge
of advocates of “naturalism,” that because we have no systematic understanding
of the relationship between the “natural” and the “supernatural,” we should ignore
the latter and focus only on the former. (Or we should “reduce” the latter to
the former.) Following the example of Plato’s analysis of ascent, in the Sun,
Line, and Cave allegories in the Republic,
Hegel shows how natural beings such as ourselves can and do come to function
in ways that can appropriately be described as “supernatural.” This functioning
merits such a description not because it belongs to a completely different
“world” than nature, but because it’s more self-determining or self-governing
than such paradigmatic “natural” processes as those studied by physics. Rather
than being two separate “worlds,” the “natural” and the (properly understood)
“supernatural” are lower and higher phases on a scale of increasing
self-government and selfhood as such.[26]
8. Hegel’s Philosophy
of Nature
In the “philosophy of
Nature” portion of his Encyclopedia, Hegel
divides Nature into “mechanics,” “physics,” and “organics.” “Organics,” of
course, has to do with life; this is what we call “biology.” “Mechanics” has to
do with the simple pushing and pulling of space, time, and matter—what I just
referred to as “physics.” What Hegel himself calls “physics” is the intervening
domain between the merely mechanical and the living, and has to do with the
organization of matter into the four elements and the planet that’s composed of
them, which unfolds as light, electricity, and chemical processes. What he
traces through this whole increasing complexity is Nature’s increasing ability
to organize itself into processes that have a “center” or a “self.” The earth,
life upon it, living species, and the life and death of individual organisms
exhibit increasingly intense versions of this “self-ness.” In all of this we
can see the process of the finite’s going beyond itself through increasing
degrees of self-determination and thus of “infinity.”
Hegel’s philosophy of
Nature is controversial not merely because of its apparently antiquated theory
of “elements” and so forth, but more importantly precisely because of the way
it focuses on “self-ness.” “Self-ness” is not an everyday concern of modern
physics, chemistry, biology, or neuroscience. On the contrary, scientists often
seem to regard it as a mere by-product of processes that they seek to
understand without reference to any “self.”
Hegel is saying,
however, that such an agenda ignores the scientist’s own fundamental experience
of seeking “selfness” in herself, through
the cognitive “ascent” that seeks to replace initial opinions and appetites
with truth. Hegel is saying that neither space, time, matter, nor anything else
can be more fundamental or better known than
this essential activity of “ascent” in which the scientist, like every human
being, is constantly engaged. So it’s legitimate to examine space, time,
matter, living things, etc. from the perspective of this issue of “self-ness,”
self-organization, and self-determination.
Indeed, it’s more legitimate to examine them from
this perspective than from any other. For self-ness (etc.) are by their very
nature the ultimate reality, in reference to which every other candidate
“reality” must be judged and understood. They are what is what it is by virtue
of itself, rather than by virtue merely of its relations to other things; so
that if we seek to understand reality as
such, and not only in its myriad “manifestations,” selfness is what we must
examine first. Since it is what we ourselves are, and what the entire activity
of investigation that we call “science” is, we know it through our mere
awareness of our own activity, and thus it’s not only more fully real but also
better known by us than anything else. To bracket what we are and what we know
best, and try to investigate only what we aren’t
and what we know less well, is to consign
ourselves to ignorance of something than which we could never know anything
more real or more fundamental.
9. And his Philosophy of
Spirit
So Hegel presents
“Spirit” as the reality that focuses most fully upon itself, inasmuch as Spirit
asks (in line with the famous injunction of the Delphic oracle to “know
thyself” [Hegel, Encyclopedia §377])
what it, “Spirit,” really is and thus how it can most successfully be what it really is.
Within “Spirit,” Hegel
unfolds first the familiar “subjective Spirit” that’s composed of our
theoretical and practical thinking. This would include the practice of science,
as well as other cognitive activities. Then Hegel examines an “objective
Spirit” that’s composed of property, morality, the family, the state, and
history. In addition to our “inner” functioning, Hegel calls all of these
“external” institutions “Spirit,” as well, because they are ways in which our
external, social world enables us to be free, self-determining, in our dealings
with one another. Enabling us to find various kinds of rational
self-determination in the external world, they prevent that world from being a
mere (irrational) obstacle to our self-determination.
But then a question
arises: which of these two kinds of freedom is primary—the internal one that’s
composed of our theoretical and practical thinking, or the external one that’s
composed of property, morality, the family, the state, and history?
Hegel’s answer is
that neither of them adequately embodies freedom, since being limited by each
other, each one outside of and opposed to the other, they are both finite. To
combine them and thus go beyond their limitations, we need a new, more
inclusive kind of reality, which will preserve what’s free and fully real in each
of them. Hegel calls this more inclusive reality “absolute Spirit” (where “absolute” means “freed”). We know this
reality as the arts, religion, and philosophy. They preserve what’s fully free
and thus fully self-determining and fully real in subjective and in objective
Spirit, and they omit the rest. So Hegel describes them as a “reconciliation.” In
fact he describes them, for reasons that I’ll explain, as “the Spirit’s
elevation to God.”[27]
10. Absolute
Spirit: Art
To begin (as Hegel
does) with art, it’s fully present in the “outer” world of the senses, but it also
goes beyond that world by giving it the additional dimension that we call
“aesthetic.” In this additional dimension, we don’t experience objective time, space,
and finite concerns in the way that we do in the “practical,”
subjective/objective world. Instead we’re held, entranced, by the aura of the
artwork and what it does to us.
It’s tempting to
describe aesthetic experience as “merely subjective,” merely “in the eye of the
beholder.” But insofar as we engage seriously with the arts, we know that this can’t
be correct. We can often reach agreement with other people about whether the art
that we make or experience together is relatively shallow and contingent, or
deeper and more compelling. That’s the sense in which the arts, while being
independent objects in the world, are also, as it were, “thoughtful.” We can
evaluate them in a way that resembles the way we evaluate thoughts. How
“compelling” are they, for those who understand them? Because of this dimension
of “thoughtfulness,” art has a more intensive presence than what’s merely
objective and lacks anything like thought. While on the other hand their
physicality gives them a more intensive presence than what’s merely subjective.
And this is what gives the
arts the magnetism that they have for us. They give us a glimpse of a more
intensive “reality,” transcending the subjective/objective divide. And we’re
inspired by this reality because we feel that we ourselves transcend that
divide, through the arts. Indeed, looking back at what’s most free and most
real in the accomplishments of subjective and objective Spirit, and of Nature
before them, we can see all of this as, in an important sense, “art.” What’s
fully “itself” and thus most real, including us, is “art” (or whatever art in its turn will turn out to be), because
in it the work, its creator, and its appreciators (as it were) “create
themselves.”
11. Absolute Spirit:
Religion and Philosophy
Since the arts enable
us to have this experience, it’s no wonder that many of us make the arts into something
rather like a religion for ourselves, in which we engage in something that’s not
very different from worship. But religion in the normal sense of the word goes one
step further than this. We can see it as an effort to consolidate or “totalize”
the magnetism that we experience in the arts.[28]
Because of their immersion in sense experience, works of art are after all
disparate, there are boundaries between them, and in that respect they fail to
achieve the full freedom, the infinity, that we’re searching for.[29]
Archetypal religious figures, on the other hand, like Jehovah, Osiris, Orpheus,
the Buddha, and Jesus overcome this disparateness and finitude by “representing,”
in various ways, the unity or infinity of everything. The “art religion” (as
Hegel calls it) of the Homeric gods is gradually displaced by the more intense,
“totalizing” religions of Orphism and its successors, because we are searching
for the complete self-determination or freedom that the latter represent for
us.
But because the world offers
us many of these “unifying” figures and associated totalizing religions, it’s
unclear whether any of them can really unify our world. And beyond that problem
there is the even more challenging problem of the division between these
figures and ourselves. This ultimately
prevents any of these figures from giving us full freedom or infinity. As
Buddhists have quipped, “If you meet the Buddha on the road, kill him.” The
Buddha may inspire you to find infinity in yourself, but if you regard him as a
figure that’s separate from yourself, he’s also an obstacle to your finding
infinity. Likewise for Jesus and all the other “gods” insofar as they are
assumed to be beings separate from ourselves.
What Hegel calls “philosophy”
supersedes this final disunity and finitude by understanding the entire process
that we see in the arts and religion, including the divisions between different
gods and between the gods and ourselves, as part of the single process of the finite’s
surpassing of itself in true infinity. Sense-experience (in art) and
representation (in religion) set us over against what we experience or what’s
represented to us. So although we came to art and religion for infinity, what
we experience in them is still, in important respects, finite. Philosophy, on
the other hand, understands us and artworks and gods as aspects of the self-comprehending process that is the
self-surpassing of everything finite, including
us, the artworks, and the gods.[30]
Within this process, everything
is integrated with everything. This is the ultimate accomplishment of the
rational love that I outlined in section 5, above. Finite, infinite, Nature,
Spirit, you, me, subjectivity, objectivity, value, science, family, state, artworks,
religion, gods—nothing is rejected, everything is integrated and subsumed, as
Spirit “raises itself to” or surpasses itself as that which alone is completely
infinite and thus wholly “itself.”
The traditional term
for what is completely infinite and wholly itself is, of course, “God.” Though
now it’s clear, as I’ve suggested, that while it’s higher, this God can’t be
separate from ourselves. Rather, as we seek to be wholly ourselves by
participating in the process that Hegel describes, we go beyond our finite
bodies, our emotional needs, all separateness from each other and from everything
else, and (as in the Roman Catholic Catechism, which is quoting Saint
Athanasius) we “become God.”
As in Plato, this
ascent is a matter of becoming (wholly) oneself, not of becoming something
different. But what one discovers about “oneself,” in the process, and what one
discovers about “God,” is certainly not what common sense or conventional
science expected. One’s true self, it turns out, is the transcendent God.
In this rather
awe-inspiring conception we see again the apparent paradox, that the merely
finite (us) can constitute, by “going beyond itself,” what’s truly infinite.
But now we have a much more detailed account of how this is possible and
(indeed) actual.[31]
12. Responses to Hegel
and to Plato
It’s not surprising
that many writers in the generation after Hegel weren’t clear about what he had
been driving at with this conception. Not recognizing the role of love in
Hegel’s ascent (on which, again, see section 5), Ludwig Feuerbach criticized it
as merely “intellectual,” and held up a counter-ideal of non-intellectual
“love” which he hoped to find in the senses and in matter.[32]
Karl Marx, focusing on the familiar misuses of religion, suspected that Hegel
and religious traditions had conceived of “Spirit” as “higher” in order to sanctify
the power of the ruling classes. Soren Kierkegaard caricatured Hegel’s “true
infinity” as a stick with which Hegel beat his opponents, and his concern for “system”
as a psychological compulsion rather than the simple effort of thought to be as
coherent as possible. And then there was Heinrich Heine’s often-quoted recollection,
“I was young and proud, and it gratified my self-esteem to learn from Hegel
that, contrary to what my grandmother thought, it wasn’t the Lord in heaven,
but I myself here on earth who was God.”[33]
This barrage of misunderstanding
all missed the point of Hegel’s ascent, which is his account of how one can be
truly oneself only by being self-determining, therefore (as we saw in section
5) not separate from anything, and since not separate, certainly not “proud.” (Likewise
it all ignored the question of what indisputably orthodox Christian writers like
Athanasius might have meant by their
notion of “becoming God.”)
To a large extent these
reactions against Hegel recapitulated reactions that had originally appeared in
response to Plato. Epicurus and Lucretius in the ancient world and Thomas
Hobbes in the 17th century responded to Plato’s apparent rejection of the
physical world by rejecting all of Plato, including the notion of “ascending”
above the mechanical functioning of bodies so as to achieve freedom. Friedrich Nietzsche,
in the 19th century, added the psychological hypothesis that when Plato and
Christians speak of something “higher” they are actually seeking a phantom compensation
or revenge for their suffering in this world. These critics all failed to see
how they themselves, insofar as they sought truth, were engaging in the ascent that
Plato and Hegel describe, and how that ascent goes beyond all issues of finite
self-interest, including any “compensation” or “revenge.”
The tradition of
rejecting both Platonism and its Hegelian version continues into our own time. If
we think of influential recent doctrines like existentialism, pragmatism, logical
positivism, materialism, naturalism, and deconstruction, none of them acknowledges
rational freedom as a means by which one can be self-determining, real as
oneself, and thus “transcendent.” Accordingly, few thinkers who are influenced
by these doctrines appreciate how the common core of science, ethics, art,
religion, and philosophy is this rational transcendence.
Despite repeated
efforts, the Plato/Hegel view has not been well expounded since Hegel’s time.[34]
But there are reasons to think that the present situation in philosophy may
make possible a new appreciation of what Plato and Hegel accomplished. In
recent decades writers such as Charles Taylor, Gary Watson, Susan Wolf, John
Martin Fischer, and Alfred Mele have developed conceptions of human rational
self-government that resemble Plato’s and Hegel’s in their general approach.[35]
Ethics and the arts are getting respectful attention; commentators on science
are doing their best to clarify the nature and the limits of science’s
understanding of reality; and not everyone regards religion as inherently and
in all respects irrational. Plato and Hegel dealt with all of these issues in a
remarkably integrated and consequently powerful way. So when a better
understanding of their response feeds into current discussions, a major illumination
could occur.
When we appreciate Plato’s and Hegel’s view we
see that science, religion, the arts, and philosophy are all aspects of the
same “ascent,” the same freedom, and the same freest and fullest reality or
“person.” And thus if science is indispensable, so are religion, ethics, the
arts, philosophy, and the fullest reality or person. To deprive oneself of any
of these, on the grounds of its supposed incompatibility with one or more of
the others, is to render oneself finite and un-free.[36]
[1] I give a good deal of additional textual support
for my way of reading Hegel in my Hegel’s
Philosophy of Reality, Freedom, and God (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2005). The “broadly Platonic” tradition, toward which I can only gesture
in this paper, seeks to overcome materialism, mechanism, nominalism,
relativism, and skepticism through a single systematic effort. (See Lloyd
Gerson’s description of “Ur-Platonism” in his From Plato to Platonism [Ithaca and London: Cornell University
Press, 2013], p. 10; and compare his Aristotle
and Other Platonists [Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 2005].)
Some leading members of the broadly Platonic tradition are Plato, Aristotle,
Plotinus, Spinoza, and Hegel.
[2] Again, more details are in Wallace (2005). I’m not
aware of another commentary that grasps Hegel’s essential proposal regarding
God or Spirit or the relevance to it of his account of infinity. I give a quick
survey of related efforts since Hegel’s time in note 36, below.
[3] Hegel’s
Science of Logic, trans. A.V.
Miller (Atlantic
Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1989) (“Miller trans.”), pp. 145 and 149; G.W.F.
Hegel, Gesammelte Werke (“GW”), vol.
21 (Hamburg: Meiner, 1985), pp. 133 and 136; G.W.F. Hegel, Theorie Werkausgabe (“TWA”) (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1969-),
vol. 5, pp. 160 and 164. In
connection with this idea of a higher degree of reality, to which Hegel refers
simply as “reality” (Realität) as
such, please note that “real” here is not to be understood primarily in
contrast to “illusory” or “imaginary” or the like. Rather, to be “real” is to
be, as its Latin root res suggests,
“thing-ish,” that is, having an inherent unity of some kind, in contrast (say)
to a mere aggregation of items. Thus A can be “more real than” B without this
implying that B is illusory or imaginary; it merely implies that B is less
organized or “itself,” and more like an aggregate. Hegel proceeds from his
introduction of “Realität” in the Science of Logic directly to the
“something” (Etwas) which he
describes as “relation to itself,” and indeed as “the beginning of the Subject”
(Hegel’s Science of Logic, Miller trans.,
p. 115; GW 21:103; TWA 5:123). When he calls the “something” the “beginning of
the Subject,” here in the Logic’s initial “Doctrine of Being,” Hegel is saying
that through its “relation to itself,” the something foreshadows what he
describes in the Logic’s culminating “Subjective Logic” as the domain of
“freedom” or self-government. So “reality,” as preliminary to the “something,”
exhibits very much in nuce the
“self-relation” and self-governing unity that we later find fully developed as
the “Subject” and its freedom. That’s another way in which, unlike the
“reality” that’s contrasted to “illusion,” etc., Hegel’s “reality” can come in
degrees. I explain in more detail in
chapter 3 of Wallace (2005) and in the whole book how this “more intensive” (Hegel’s Science of Logic, Miller trans.,
p. 137; GW 21:125; TWA 5:150)
“reality” of infinite freedom is the theme of Hegel’s philosophical system as a
whole.
[4] By contrasting us with automatons, I don’t mean to
take any position regarding determinism or libertarian free will, as such. I’m
merely drawing attention to our need to take seriously our own rational
functioning as enabling us to go beyond pre-given appetites and opinions. If we
can’t actually function in this way, we might as well abandon the idea that we
can practice science or any other rational discipline.
[5] Michael A. Sells, ed., Early Islamic Mysticism (New York: Paulist Press, 1996), p. 151.
Teachers like Rabia, who don’t focus on an “afterlife” as such, don’t reduce
religion to mere morality, insofar as they are concerned with the fuller
“reality” or God that is achieved through the “ascent” of which morality is one
aspect. This is the way in which “mystical” traditions, which are concerned
with the eternal present rather than with an “afterlife,” are still fully
“religious.”
[6] On the issue of how to translate this famous line
in Luke, see Ilaria Ramelli, “Luke 17:21: ‘The kingdom of God is inside you.’
The Ancient Syriac Versions in Support of the Correct Translation” (2009),
available on-line (March 2013).
[7] For example, “The Word of God
became man, that thou mayest learn from man how man can become God” (Clement of
Alexandria, Exhortation to the Heathen,
ch. 1, par. 871). For other examples
see the Wikipedia article, “Divinization [Christian],” citing among many other
sources the Catechism of the Catholic
Church; and for commentary see Michael J. Christensen and Jeffery A.
Wittung, eds., Partakers of the Divine
Nature (Cranbury, NJ: Associated University Presses, 2007). See also St.
Augustine’s famous saying, “You [that is, God] were more inward [to me] than my
most inward part” (Confessions,
III.vi [11]).
[8] “It will be found that in the very act of keeping
the infinite pure and aloof from the finite, the infinite is only made finite”
(Miller trans., p. 137; GW 21:124; TWA 5:149). It’s probably clear by now that
as is usually true in theological discussions, the kind of “infinity” that
Hegel is discussing here is a “qualitative” infinity rather than a mathematical
or quantitative one. He discusses mathematical infinities in the second section
(“Quantity”) of the Logic’s “Doctrine
of Being.” The relation between the two types of infinity, as Hegel presents
it, is too complex for me to discuss here.
[9] See Paul Tillich, Systematic Theology, vol. 2 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1957), pp. 6-7, and Karl Rahner, Foundations of
Christian Faith (London: Darton,
Longman and Todd, 1978), p. 63. One could
also mention Alfred North Whitehead, Charles Hartshorne, Jürgen Moltmann, David
Ray Griffin, and Philip Clayton, all of whom are usefully surveyed in John
Culp, “Panentheism,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on-line (2008 and
2013).
[10] “Hegel seemed to be denying any kind of
transcendence (at least in a non-trivial sense) to God” (Terry Pinkard, German Philosophy 1760-1860. The Legacy of
Idealism [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002], p. 303). Compare
William Desmond, Hegel’s God: A
Counterfeit Double? (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2003), p. 2, and Stephen Houlgate,
The Opening of Hegel’s Logic: From Being
to Infinity (West Lafayette, IN: Purdue University Press, 2006), p. 435. As
evidence of Hegel’s rejection of transcendence, A. W. Moore in his The Evolution of Modern Metaphysics: Making
Sense of Things ([Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012], p. 178)
cites Hegel’s Encyclopedia §38, in
which I assume he’s referring to Hegel’s objection there to the notion of a
“beyond” (Jenseits), which Hegel
associates with the “Ought.” But Hegel in fact approves of a certain kind of
“beyond-ness,” which is the way in which true infinity, in his words, “goes
beyond” the finite. See note 13, below, for the key citation on this. I
discussed this whole issue in section 3.17 (pp. 96-102) of Wallace (2005).
[11] “Theism,” as Charles Taylor puts it, “looks on the
world as created by a God who is separate and independent of the universe,” and
“this cannot be accepted by Hegel” (Hegel
[Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975], p. 100.
[12] Hegel does occasionally use the adjective,
“immanent,” in roughly the sense that Kant gave to it (Critique of Pure Reason A296f.), as pertaining to the realm of what
can be known. Unless one assumes (as Hegel does not) that God cannot be known,
this kind of “immanence” has nothing directly to do with our notion of
immanence as the opposite of (“orthodox”) divine transcendence.
[13] Transcendere means literally “to climb over, surmount,
surpass,” and Hegel explicitly describes the infinite as “going beyond” the
finite: “The infinite is only as a going beyond [als Hinausgehen über] the finite” (Hegel’s Science of Logic, trans. Miller, p. 145 [Miller’s
translation actually says “transcending”!]; TWA 5:160; GW 21:133). So we have
to be careful not to read too much into Hegel’s objection to notions of a “Jenseits” (a “beyond”). In the next
sentence but one after the sentence that I just quoted, Hegel spells out what
it is that he really objects to: “The finite is not sublated by the infinite as
by a power existing outside it; on the contrary, its infinity consists in
sublating its own self.” What he objects to is not the notion of going beyond,
as such, but the notion that such going beyond involves or is brought about by
“a power existing outside” the finite. That is, he objects to conceptions of
the “beyond” as a separately existing being. So rather than rejecting
“transcendence” as such, Hegel is presenting what amounts to a revised
conception of it, what we might call a “true
transcendence.” (As for being “real as itself,” Hegel’s whole discussion in the Science
of Logic of the “something” and the “finite” is a discussion of how
something can be fully “in itself” and thus “real” [Miller trans. p. 111-115,
GW 21:98-102, TWA 5:118-122], and the upshot is that the infinite is what’s
“real” [Miller trans. p. 149, GW 21:136, TWA 5:164] and thus “in itself.”)
[14] Plato undermines the idea that God is an
“independently existing being” when he makes it clear in the Timaeus that the “craftsman” who created
the world had no choice but to create it, because he was “without jealousy”
(29e). That is, God’s nature requires God to create a world; so we can’t
coherently conceive of a God without a world; so the two don’t “exist
independently” of each other in the usual sense. Plato’s conception of
phenomena “participating in” transcendent Forms likewise suggests a closer
relationship than the two “existing independently” of each other. Plato
and Hegel both make it clear that it doesn’t follow from X’s not being a
separate being from Y, that X is identical to Y. It may instead be the case
that X “participates in” Y (Plato) or that Y is the “self-surpassing” of X
(Hegel: see the text quoted in note 15).
[15] To quote Hegel’s formulation again: “The infinite is only as a going beyond the finite….
The finite is not sublated by the infinite as by a power existing outside it;
on the contrary, its infinity consists in sublating its own self” (Hegel’s Science of Logic, trans. Miller,
p. 146; TWA 5:160; GW 21:133).
[17] “Mutual repulsion and
flight is not a liberation from what is repelled and fled from; the one as
excluding still remains connected to what is excluded” (Science of Logic, Miller
trans., p. 175 [translation revised]; GW 21:163; TWA 5:196).
[18] The free alternative to being guided by one’s
separateness from others is not being guided by what we merely happen to share
with others, but rather being guided by our shared search for the True and the
Good. So the love that Plato and Hegel advocate isn’t indiscriminate promotion
of whatever we all happen to want, but rather a fostering of rational freedom
in each and all of us. Which is a fostering that undoubtedly will often involve
promoting the material conditions that enable such rational freedom to be
actualized in us.
[19] “Supremely free”: Science of Logic Miller trans. p. 841, GW 12:251, TWA 6:570. At
Miller trans. p. 824, GW 12:236, TWA 6:549, Hegel spells out “personality” as
involving being “for itself” rather than “for” (dependent on) anything else,
and being “practical” (as well as theoretical or contemplative). Nurturing:
“The universal…could also be called free
love … for it bears itself toward what it is different from as toward itself” (Miller trans., p.
603, GW 12:35, TWA 6:277).
[20] On Aristotle’s contribution to Platonism in a
broad and useful sense of the word, see Lloyd Gerson, Aristotle and Other Platonists (Ithaca and London: Cornell
University Press, 2005). I should acknowledge that Plato’s middle-period
preoccupation with the “separation” (chorismos)
of the Forms vis-à-vis what “participates” in them prefigures our conventional
assumption that God is a “separate” being. But it’s well-known that Plato in
his Parmenides criticizes this
“separation” trenchantly—without showing any sign of abandoning his fundamental
concern with “ascent.” This is how the broad Platonic tradition that includes
Aristotle and Hegel gets under way.
[21] Hegel’s first major work, his Phenomenology of Spirit (1807), rotated around the same issue of
subject and object, but complicated it in ways that the Science of Logic and Encyclopedia
avoided. So it’s easier to extract his fundamental thought from the Logic and Encyclopedia than from the Phenomenology.
[23] Encyclopedia
Logic §95 Remark. One could
suggest that insofar as there is a distinction between the infinite and the
finite, there is still a separation and a “relation” between them. But Hegel’s
point is precisely that in this distinctness, they still depend upon each other
(since “The infinite is only as a
going beyond the finite” [see note 3 above]) for their identity. So the
“relation” between them is not, like ordinary relations, “external” to their
identity.
[24] “At the name of the infinite, the heart and the mind
or spirit [the Gemüt and the Geist] light up, for in the infinite the
mind or spirit is not merely abstractly present to itself, but rises to its own
self, to the light of its thinking, of its universality, of its freedom” (Science of Logic, trans. Miller, p. 138; GW 21:125; TWA 5:150).
[25] Plato explains how the Good enables the soul to be
unified and to function as “itself” in Republic
book iv (on reason in the soul) and books vi-vii (on reason and the Good).
Hegel discusses the “Ought” in Science of
Logic, Miller trans., pp.131-136,
GW 21:118-123, TWA 5:142-148, and the Good itself in Science of Logic pp. 818-823, GW 12:231-235, TWA 6:541-548.
Commentators often stress Hegel’s criticisms of Kant’s and Fichte’s misleading
conception of the “ought” to such an extent that they neglect the “ought’s” key
role, for Hegel, in indicating how the finite can in fact go beyond itself as
the infinite. We have to ask why the “ought” becomes an issue here at all, in
the Logic’s conceptual development. If it were merely a “blind alley,” it would
be the only “blind alley” in the Logic. It’s more plausible to understand it as
Hegel’s acknowledgement that Kant and Fichte genuinely seek, through the
“ought,” to go beyond finitude, and that such a seeking indicates the possibility of what it unfortunately
fails to achieve. The prominent role of the Good at the conclusion of the Logic and the alternation of ontological
topics with practical ones in the Encyclopedia
make it clear that the ontological implications that Hegel associates with
the “ought” introduce us to a fundamental principle of his system.
[26] In this way, Hegel’s “idealism” (as he calls it)
does not assert like George Berkeley’s idealism that all reality is ideas
located in minds, or like Kant’s idealism that important features are imposed
on reality by minds. Rather, it shows how what most deserves to be called
“real,” because it’s self-governing and thus is what it is by virtue of itself,
is minds or “spirit.” The processes studied by physics are real in the sense
that they can be studied objectively, but not in the sense that they are what
they are by virtue of themselves. This is the gist of Hegel’s definitive
account of what he means by “idealism,” in Science
of Logic Miller trans. pp.154-156,
GW 21:142-143, TWA 5:172-173.
[27] “Reconciliation”: Encyclopedia §§552R, 555, 561, TWA 10:364, 367, 369. “Spirit’s
elevation to God”: Encyclopedia §552R,
TWA 10:354; compare §50 Remark, TWA 8:132.
[28] In Encyclopedia
§572 Hegel lays out the sequence of Art, Religion, and Philosophy as
embodying (respectively) “intuition” (Anschauung),
“representation” (Vorstellung) and
“self-conscious thought,” and he associates religion and “representation” with
“totality” (Totalität).
[29] This is a way of stating Plato’s objection to the
arts, in the Republic, that they are
“images of images,” and so forth. But it’s clear from Plato’s own manifestly
artistic efforts (which he himself occasionally acknowledges as such) that
while philosophy surpasses the arts in principle, it doesn’t thereby render
them dispensable. Hegel formalizes this state of affairs by presenting the arts
as aspects of “absolute Spirit,” ultimately subsumed but not abolished by
philosophy, in accordance with his principles of “sublation” (Aufhebung) and true infinity.
[30] “This knowledge is thus the concept, cognized by
thought, of Art and Religion, in which the diverse elements in the content are
cognized as necessary, and this necessary as free” (Encyclopedia §572, TWA 10:378).
[31] When in the Encyclopedia’s
treatment of Spirit everything finite goes beyond itself, as what Hegel now
calls “the self-thinking Idea,” it
“goes back” to his Logic (Encyclopedia §574),
in which the culminating “Idea” was the origin of Nature and Spirit. Nature and
Spirit always presupposed that infinity, and now they have explicitly returned
to it. Thus Nature and Spirit are the epistrophe
or turning back that (following the traditional pattern first spelled out
by Plotinus) reverses the proodos, “progression,”
or flowing out that occurs, in Hegel, in the Logic. Plotinus’s epistrophe was modeled on Plato’s
descriptions of ascent in Republic book
vii (etc.) and his proodos was modeled
on Plato’s creation story in the Timaeus.
Hegel has shown us a way in which to understand these traditional concepts.
[32] It’s sometimes suggested that Feuerbach’s
“anthropotheism” restates what was really going on in Hegel’s philosophical
theology. This, however, is a mistake, because Feuerbach didn’t reproduce the
vertical dimension of (Plato’s and) Hegel’s thinking, which corresponds to
religion’s “transcendence.” This is why Feuerbach’s various proposals have not
inspired or attracted much of a following.
[33] Heinrich Heine, Confessions, trans. P. Heinegg (n.p.: Joseph Simon, 1981),
p. 47.
[34] During the two centuries since Hegel, a series of
writers have tried either to explain how the Plato/Hegel synthesis works or to
state something similar in their own way. In his The World as Will and Representation (1818), Arthur Schopenhauer laid
out a duality of “will,” on the one hand, and a blissful liberation from “will”
(vol. 2, pars. 65-70), on the other. But because Schopenhauer didn’t bring out
the significance of our pursuit of the true and the good, or rational
transcendence, there was no apparent path that could lead from “will” to the
liberation that Schopenhauer described. Hence, no doubt, his pessimism. Later,
Friedrich Nietzsche, Martin Heidegger, and Jean-Paul Sartre wrote about
becoming oneself, authenticity, and freedom, but none of them noted how the
pursuit of the true and the good can be crucial in this connection, by raising
one above automatic responses to one’s heritage or environment. Francis Herbert
Bradley, in his Appearance and Reality (1893),
gave a version of Hegel that likewise neglected the role of rational
transcendence in becoming fully oneself and thus provided no path that an
individual could travel from “appearance” to mystical “reality.” Like
Schopenhauer and Bradley, Ludwig Wittgenstein’s apparently positive allusions
to “the mystical” in his Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus (1921) didn’t connect it to our everyday experience of
rational transcendence and thus they left obscure the role of this “mystical”
in our lives. John Niemeyer Findlay and Wilfrid Sellars, in the middle of the
century, and John McDowell’s Mind and
World (1992) and Iris Murdoch’s Metaphysics
as a Guide to Morals (1992) likewise didn’t clarify the role of rational transcendence
in (full) reality, and thus they weren’t able to effectively overcome scientism’s
notion of “reality” as simply what’s “objective.” R.G. Collingwood came close
to Hegel’s project of integration in his Speculum
Mentis (1924), but he too did not spell out the notion of rational
transcendence as such. Alfred North Whitehead identified the Platonic rational
transcendence in general terms in his Religion
in the Making (1926) and Process and
Reality (1929), but he didn’t articulate it in everyday terms as freedom
and love, so the concrete relevance of his account has remained fairly obscure.
Nor have commentators on Hegel from Findlay through Charles Taylor, H.S.
Harris, Robert Pippin, Stephen Houlgate, Peter Hodgson, or (in Germany) Dieter
Henrich or Walter Jaeschke brought out the centrality of rational transcendence
in Hegel’s system. So rational transcendence has not been effectively presented
since Hegel’s time, and Nietzsche’s, Bertrand Russell’s, and Heidegger’s
influential critiques of Platonism and Hegel have not been effectively
countered.
[35] I’m referring to Charles Taylor’s “Responsibility
for Self,” first published in A. O. Rorty, ed., The Identities of Persons (Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press, 1976), pp. 281-299, and not to Taylor’s Hegel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975), in which he
unfortunately did not identify or appreciate Hegel’s contribution to the same
Platonic train of thought about rational self-government that he (Taylor) was
pursuing in “Responsibility for Self.”
[36] I would like to thank Tom Bennigson, Thomas Burns,
and Alan Montefiore for very helpful comments on drafts of this paper.
very informative blog about religion...
ReplyDeleteReal stories
This comment has been removed by a blog administrator.
ReplyDeleteThis comment has been removed by a blog administrator.
ReplyDeleteThis comment has been removed by a blog administrator.
ReplyDeleteVery illuminating Robert, congratulations. Felt like I went beyond my finitude a little bit while reading it.😁
ReplyDeleteBogdan
Thank you, Bogdan. What we all dream of, eh?
ReplyDelete